This entry is dedicated to equal
marriage opportunity and the Constitution.
A series of cases will come before
the Supreme Court this year pertaining to recognition of marriages for same-sex
couples. These cases will address
various issues, some relating to the states, some to the federal government (challenging
the constitutionality of the Defense of Marriage Act). The Court here faces a complex set of
questions. I will address but one.
Does the Constitution require that
the states recognize marriages between same-sex couples?
To begin, I
will separate this issue along two lines.
As a legislative matter, this issue seems very clear-cut to me. I have been able to glean little more than a
naked distaste for homosexuality and a deep-seated animus against homosexuals driving
the laws and constitutional amendments in the states prohibiting legal
recognition of those unions. Were I to
sit on any state’s legislature, I would be honored to vote for a statute
recognizing marriages between same-sex couples.
I would be similarly honored to vote for state constitutional amendments
to that end, or to vote against amendments outlawing such recognition (as I did
in Florida in 2008).
But the
policy of marriage recognition is different from its constitutionality.
This
question raises competing claims: the Constitution’s demand that the states
provide the equal protection of the laws, and the states’ police power: their
undifferentiated authority to regulate on behalf of the health, safety, welfare,
and morals of their citizens. The states
have historically dictated the terms of the marriages they will recognize with
few exceptions (like the Court’s intervention in Loving v. Virginia, which ruled that a Virginia law prohibiting
interracial marriages violated equal protection). Defining the terms of marriage drives to the
heart of the states’ police powers.
The Court
has spoken on issues involving state action and homosexuality before. Important cases like Lawrence v. Texas and Romer
v. Evans set a precedent for equal treatment toward those of whatever
sexual orientation, though they conspicuously declined to name sexual
orientation as a protected class under EP jurisprudence.
Lawrence
involved the invalidation of a Texas statute criminalizing sexual activity
between same-sex couples. The Court’s
majority opinion relied on a right to privacy grounded in the Due Process
Clause of the 14th Amendment, and recent decisions elaborating (creating?)
that right. Justice Stevens, writing the
majority opinion in Lawrence, made a
special effort to foreclose the possibility that his opinion would be used in
future cases to impose same-sex marriage recognition on the states by
distinguishing this case from a hypothetical one involving marriage recognition
by implying that the states would have an interest in reserving marriage for heterosexual
couples. But more pertinent to this
discussion is Justice O’Connor’s (more cogent) concurrence noting that to
prohibit sexual conduct for homosexuals but not for heterosexuals constitutes a
violation of Equal Protection insofar as such a law treats similarly situated
people differently without a rational basis.
Romer
overruled an amendment to the Colorado constitution forbidding anyone to claim
protection from Colorado’s anti-discrimination laws on grounds of sexual
orientation. Stevens, writing for the
majority again, unearthed as the amendment’s motivation nothing more than a
transparent prejudice against homosexuals.
But again, he declined to say anything more than that these laws failed
the rational basis test
Justice Scalia’s scathing dissent
in Lawrence reveals inconsistency in
the majority opinion, but also could portend the future: the Court’s opinion
delves deeply into American and common law history to find and distinguish the
motivations behind anti-sodomy laws from modern statutes like Texas’. Such a painstaking analysis reaches far
beyond normal rational-basis jurisprudence into the demanding standards of
strict-scrutiny review. The Court acts
disingenuously when it says one thing and does another. However, such an argument may reveal that the
Court was merely unwilling to reveal its true intentions at that time. The full revelation of this more exacting
standard of review may await us this year.
However, both
of these cases differ from the issues at hand: they forbid the states from
engaging in discrimination, but they do not require legal recognition of marriages
between same-sex couples. There is a
difference between a laissez-faire approach to personal relationships between
consenting adults, and the active recognition of such relations’ equality
before the law and the polity. Hands-off
is different from thumbs-up.
However,
one could say that Romer does involve
equal recognition of homosexuals in the states before the law insofar as it
deals with self-identification along lines of sexual orientation, which in turn
depends on sexual conduct. Perhaps this
case does involve thumbs-up recognition insofar as it demands that the states
regard homosexuals legally as they would any other identifiable group. Lawrence
similarly involves non-discrimination along lines of sexual conduct (although
again, Stevens denied to expand such recognition into the marital arena), and
insistence that to criminalize certain sexual conduct stigmatizes those who
engage in it, weakening regard for the law.
Both themes are present also in Romer,
as arguably in any case challenging state failure to recognize same-sex
marriage. Such failure arguably
perpetuates a stigma against homosexuals and homosexual conduct by enshrining
it in law; further, such failure denies to homosexual couples the full measure
of the law’s protection in such matters as taxation and inheritance.
(I don’t
know enough about civil unions to know whether this is strictly true, but in
the event that they are not equal in such matters strengthens the EP argument.)
Still, Lawrence mainly involves a hands-off
policy toward homosexual relations more than it involves an active recognition
and approval of such unions. I’ve tried
in the previous paragraph to argue as strongly as possible for active state
recognition on Lawrence and Romer’s precedent. But even Romer
strictly requires the states not to disqualify sexual orientation as a
protected class under their non-discrimination laws. This decision did not require recognition of
such a group, only that they not be disqualified out of hand. It’s a stretch to say that the Court’s
previous decisions regarding homosexuality pave the way for legal recognition
of marriage between such couples. Again,
even Lawrence required only that the
state’s coercive mechanisms not be used to stigmatize homosexuality and invade
the privacy of adults’ bedrooms. Romer dealt with nothing so private as
sexual intimacy.
The federal
government has traditionally kept its hands off state regulations of
marriage. A notable recent exception was
the case Loving v. Virginia in which
the Supreme Court invalidated a Virginia stature forbidding interracial
marriages on Equal Protection grounds.
The state had claimed that it was not treating the races unequally,
since both white people and black people were subject to the same restrictions:
neither group was allowed to intermarry.
In striking down the law, the Court declared that the right to marry was
fundamental to individual liberty, and that such separation of the races
necessarily violated equal protection despite its ostensibly equal treatment
(both races were forbidden from intermarrying, but practically the Court
understood that the legal and social burden would fall to black people).
Most important in this case for our
purposes is Earl Warren’s declaration that the freedom to marry is fundamental. Clearly, Loving
pertains to racial inequalities, but it sets a precedent that the federal
government will not hesitate to examine how states regulate marriage if certain
lines of fairness are crossed.
Are they
crossed here?
Equal
Protection jurisprudence has recognized five classes against which
discrimination will trigger heightened review: race, gender, alienage,
illegitimacy, and exercising constitutional rights (the last is seldom used;
usually the right at issue defends whoever exercises it without recourse to the
EP Clause). Sexual orientation is not
among them. Again, Romer and Lawrence
involved no more than rational-basis review, requiring no greater scrutiny than
cursory examination.
So, the
Court has not recognized that sexual orientation is a “discrete and insular
minority” (U.S. v. Carolene Products Co.):
deserving special protection because of political powerlessness, with a history
of invidious discrimination. As such,
discrimination along lines of sexual orientation triggers the same standard of
review as would state discrimination against any other lines, which is almost
always permissible.
Should discrimination
against homosexuals trigger heightened review?
Few would dispute that this group has been victimized by discrimination in
American history; they have indeed been victims of onerous discrimination. And because social stigmas force many
homosexuals (or those who question the certainty of their sexual orientation)
to remain in hiding, this minority remains politically vulnerable due to its
small size and disorganization. It
should not surprise—it is barely worth mentioning—that homosexuals are
underrepresented in the political process.
There are surely far fewer openly gay legislators and other politicians
in proportion to the population at large.
However, on the other hand, how discrete and immutable is this minority is questionable, since many consider
sexuality to be a spectrum rather than a zero-sum game. Still, homosexuals cannot change their
orientation at a whim; this much should be apparent and accepted in the present
day. We should have long ago left behind
the notion that homosexuals can be “cured” or otherwise treated for their
“condition”. However, sexual orientation
is difficult to demonstrate, as opposed to race or gender, which are usually
immediately apparent. Thus, it would be
easy for conniving individuals to take advantage of any special dispensations
afforded homosexuals under non-discrimination laws.
Though
homosexuals may not qualify as a discrete class, others fail to meet the
criteria fully as well. For example, women
comprise slightly over half the American population; as such they cannot even
be thought of as a minority, let alone one discrete and insular. Though women have clearly been considered
subordinates, and have been badly victimized by a political process to which
they were not privy for generations, gender discrimination does not fit the EPC
bill entirely. As such, perhaps the best
place for sexual orientation discrimination lies in the same category of
mid-level scrutiny due to gender discrimination.
Now, to
argue for the opposite side: this case implicates the powers of the states.
Once again,
I will not address religious arguments, assuming for the moment that such laws
founded on purely religious grounds would violate the Establishment Clause as
incorporated against the states by Everson
v. Board of Education (establishment) and Cantwell v. Connecticut (free exercise). Solely on constitutional grounds, federal involvement
in marriage runs up against the states’ police powers, which has traditionally
involved regulation and recognition of marriage as part of their power to
regulate on behalf of their citizens’ morals.
Further,
the political power of homosexuals and their allies is growing, demonstrated by
some states’ legalization of marriage equality in the 2012 elections. The national trend may be shifting in this
direction, taking the wind out of the sails of any judicial efforts to remove
this issue from the political process.
If this process fixes its problems on its own, there is no need for
judges to step in. Indeed, I posit that
they have a duty not to become
involved absent pervasive, persistent, and invidious inequalities in the
political process.
Regulating
marriage drives right to the heart of these powers, especially as they have
been eroded over time. Though the
federal government has the power and an interest in promoting and ensuring
equality, the states have an interest in safeguarding those powers that still
redound to them in an era in which most issues of substantive concern are
resolved at the national level.
If the
federal government nationalizes marriage, what will remain to the states? If either the Congress or the Supreme Court
exercises its 14th Amendment power to require all the states to
recognize same-sex marriages, little will remain of their once-sovereign
power. Few issues drive deeper to the
heart of the police power than regulating public morality, since today much of regulation
on behalf of health and welfare is either handled by the federal government, or
at least conceived from the top, and only executed on the bottom. The expansion of federal commerce power to
near limitlessness has enervated the states’ power to act for the health and
safety of their citizens; to strike at public morality nearly destroys state
sovereignty altogether.
Moreover,
the scenario presented above does not entail a Congressional act dictating
rules of marriage recognition nationwide, but the Supreme Court claiming that
such is the command of the Constitution.
Congress can only enact legislation appropriate to enforce the 14th
Amendment; the Court would implicate the issue in the Constitution itself. The distinction is important. The people can, if they choose, order that
Congress reverse a statute. A Supreme
Court opinion can only be overturned by Constitutional amendment, or by a
future Court decision. The latter
scenario largely cuts the people out of the equation, ostensibly (and ironically?)
by invoking the people’s highest will and supreme law.
Using statutory
law to enforce marriage equality presents a different problem: what to do when
the bare national majorities drawn on party lines shift Congressional
power. What happens to this hypothetical
statute when Congress falls into conservatives’ hands again? What happens when the small national liberal
majority tilts back toward the Republicans? Constant vibrations in national public policy
compromise the predictability necessary to the legal system,
One lesson
that the nation should take from the abortion struggles is that a Supreme Court
decision claiming a segment of public policy for its very own can stoke the
flames of a debate that may have otherwise simmered more civilly. With Roe
v. Wade and subsequent cases, the people lost their voice; the policy
choice became mysteriously and questionably embedded in the Constitution rather
than decided by the people at large, or within their states. This frustration may have caused the debate
to become more acrimonious that it might have done otherwise (several states
had begun moving to liberalize their abortion laws before Roe), the bitter backlash sparking a defensive response from other
parts of the public.
Those who
disagree with given Supreme Court decisions are cut out of the political
process. Participation in this process
should be seen as a positive good in itself, an example of the civic virtue without
which a democracy cannot function.
The bottom
line: when the Court implicates social issues in the Constitution without clear
mandate, it removes a segment of the people’s power to decide issues for ourselves,
which is understandably frustrating.
Furthermore, such decisions come dangerously close to making the Court
into a roving super-legislature, creating public policy under the guise of
Constitutional mandate and judicial review, but without the check of popular
accountability. This is arguably a
violation of the separation of powers and due process of law.
My refusal
to endorse a Supreme Court decision imposing marriage equality on the states
stems not from any prejudice against homosexuals, but a respect for the
political process, and concern for the Constitution’s legitimacy, endangered by
its persistent use in resolving contentious social ills. The more we force the Constitution to take
sides in our political debates, the more we risk fracturing the polity it
constitutes irreconcilably. It is cast
in general principles, standing above the everyday political struggles that
define our democratic order.
No comments:
Post a Comment