Toward the end of Lawrence Tribe’s
book, The Invisible Constitution, he
makes a curious claim: that a rule barring state secession was established more
on the Civil War battlefields battlefield than the halls of courtrooms,
congresses, or constitutional conventions.
I don’t find this persuasive. Especially in light of recent (admittedly
half-hearted) secession petitions making the rounds online since the 2012
presidential elections, it seems opportune to make a constitutional argument
against secession—why secession is forbidden legally, not martially.
The Constitution’s text contains no
mention of secession, so we will have to confront general themes and principles
of the document—parts of what Tribe would call the “invisible constitution”: implicit
facets of the written document
A Word for Secession
I’ll begin by using Tribe’s
geodesic model: certain provisions of the constitution require tightly bounded
expansions, or shields, to protect the full meaning and implications of
explicit textual provisions.
For example, here an expansive
reading of the 10th Amendment may even suggest that the states
retain sovereignty enough to go their own way should they so choose. After all, the federal government nowhere
empowered to prevent secession; therefore, secession remains to the states as
an option should they choose to do so.
It’s worth noting that such an
interpretation would require at least a myopic reading of the Necessary and
Proper Clause, if not virtually ignoring the concept entirely. But if any or all of the federal government’s
domestic powers are to remain robust, or perhaps even to mean anything at all,
the geodesic model (as contemplated by the NPC) must apply to congressional
powers as well.
Argument Summary
None of Congress’ domestic powers
can be effective if the states are free to leave (and thus to negate federal
law) with impunity at any point they choose.
Also limits federal policymaking if
the states have that threat to hold over the government (game theory of
policymaking—limited by what the states are willing to accept; neglects true
locus of government decision-making and accountability: the people)
Also,
constitutional power-ups like the Necessary and Proper Clause and the Supremacy
Clause would amount practically to nothing. The states’ ultimate trump card would severely
cuff federal legislators; they could not implement the full measure of their
powers or of their preferred policies for fear of driving even one state to
lawful secession. Each state’s
consequent veto power would make the supremacy of federal law exclusively
ceremonial, and make the Necessary and Proper Clause an empty letter.
Of
particular note, I think, is the little-noted Republican Clause in Article IV,
on which the only case I know of that dealt with secession (Texas v. White)
rested. The federal government cannot
guarantee to every state a republican form of government if such states are
free to unshackle themselves from federal control at any moment.
Texas v. White
The only
case I’ve read which dealt with the legal issues surrounding secession, White dealt with loans which Texas had
accrued during the Civil War; following the war’s end, (I believe that) Texas
claimed that since it had made those loans as an independent nation whose
government had since collapsed, the loans were invalidated, and the state bore
no continued duty to repay them.
The Supreme
Court ruled otherwise, declaring that Texas could not leave the Union; its
supposedly new government had been entirely illegitimate, and as such the true
legislature of the state was on the hook for the borrowed cash. The Court hung its decision on the Republican
Clause in Article IV, reasoning that the federal government would be deprived
of its duty and power to guarantee each state a republican form of government
if secession were legally permissible.
This is the
closest—I believe—that the nation or the Court has come to addressing the
theory and legality of state secession.
I agree completely with the Court’s reasoning: without a tacit
prohibition on secession, federal power, including the Republican Clause, would
amount to almost nothing.
This is especially true if one
notices that Congress has also a duty to exercise certain of its enumerated
powers; if not a duty written into the Constitution, then surely there is an
expectation that such powers delegated will be responsibly and fruitfully
exercised. If the people, through their
ordaining Constitution, gave certain powers to the Congress in the hopes that
their nation would therefore become more perfect, then any state interference
arising from a threat to dismember the union should not only engender outrage
from the people, but legal condemnation on the grounds that such renders the
Constitution’s plan moot, and places the states above the people as the
nation’s ultimate sovereign.
Enervation of Domestic
Powers
Such a principle implicates many of
the other domestic powers of Congress.
For
example, the power over interstate commerce: how can Congress regulate
interstate commerce if the states are free to bail, and thus to frustrate any
such regulations whenever they choose?
Further,
the power over the common defense: a state free to leave at any point could
easily become a staging ground for foreign invasion, a concept perhaps largely
irrelevant in the modern era, but not when the Constitution was ratified (and
possibly relevant again in the future).
The threat
of such departure, as well, would give each state an essential veto power,
making Congress timid with the exercise of any of these powers. Any and all federal domestic powers would
amount to very little if the states could express a veto over all such
regulations at any time by secession.
Though a blunt instrument, secession would produce a chilling effect on
everything Congress does; any and every regulation, expenditure, tax, etc.
would have to be passed so as not to offend the people or legislature of a
particular state.
Such
chilling effects go well beyond the normal hesitation lawmakers must feel when
enacting policy that risks offending their constituents. I’m all for limiting Congress’ powers more
than the present state of affairs evinces, but the power of such a threat goes
beyond mere limitation into emasculation, rendering Congress’ powers largely
ceremonial or hypothetical.
The federal
government cannot operate on the individual citizens when the states can
intervene at any point by seceding.
If the
federal government may not act on the citizens directly, then we have no union;
we have a confederacy.
A
confederacy is precisely what we had with the Articles of Confederation.
The
Constitution was erected to fix the problems of confederacy.
Therefore,
we cannot have a confederacy because the Constitution cannot be construed to
recreate the very problems it was built to ameliorate.
Foreign Policy and
Incomplete Sovereignty
And on that
note, it bears brief mention that the states do not possess the full measure of
typical sovereign authority, especially in the realm of foreign relations (e.g.
CASES). As such, to secede would not
just be to exercise a reserved domestic power as discussed under the 10th
Amendment above, but also to assume to the state the powers over foreign
affairs expressly delegated to Congress.
To exercise the full measure of a sovereign nation’s powers in that
manner is usurpation, not merely a necessary option in the residuum of state
power.
Secession Procedures,
or the Impracticability Thereof
If secession were a viable option,
surely there would be in the plan that bound the states together some procedure
for departure. In the absence of such a
plan, what would constitute an acceptable method?
As a hypothetical scenario: imagine
a federal law so unpopular in a state that its citizens hold a secession vote. Let us say for now that the law in question is
the Affordable Care Act (Obamacare); this seems appropriate in light of the
public outcry, and the refusal of several governors to accept federal funds to
implement it. Let us suppose that the
state legislature chooses to send a secession bill to the citizens, who pass it
narrowly by referendum.
What would
happen to all the people in the state who want to stay?
How could
the federal government guarantee a republican form of government to this new
government in the future?
Leaving
this hypothetical momentarily: without any standardized secession procedure,
what if a state legislature voted to secede against the wishes of a majority of
the state’s residents?
In sum, what would an
acceptable secession procedure be? If
the Constitution does not say, then how could it be determined? Excessive confusion would ensue if each state
were responsible for determining its own secession procedures—if a state
legislature did vote to secede against its citizens wishes, then how would a
newly elected body, sent to mend ties with the Union, go about
re-entering? The normal procedures for
admitting new states into the union did not contemplate incorporating (or
re-incorporating) sovereign nations.
14th
Amendment
A brief word on the 14th
Amendment: the themes covered here are the same as those relevant to other
Congressional powers, but the 14th Amendment, because of its importance in
modern American law, deserves singling out among those amendments which grant
Congress enforcement powers beyond the powers in Articles I and IV.
This amendment so radically changed the relationship between the states and the
federal government that its enervation spells special trouble for the people as
a whole, should a theory of secession so emasculate Congressional power as I
predict it would. See Akhil Amar’s “The
Bill of Rights as a Constitution” for further elaboration on this point, but
for the moment, trust that the 14th Amendment’s powers changed the
federal government into a sentinel over the states, the defender of the
trampled minority. To exhaust that power
by threat of lawful secession would spell the end, essentially, of the 14th
Amendment’s powers. Imagine if Arkansas
had felt itself unbound by federal power, unrestrained by the Constitution, and
free to depart at its pleasure after Brown. There may never have been a Cooper v. Aaron; indeed, there may never
have been a Brown at all. Perhaps there only would have been a feeble
federal government too concerned with another Civil War, or at least too
concerned with a fractured union, to do anything about segregation.
The Equal Protection Clause’s right to interstate travel
also would fall. This isn’t worth as
much discussion as the prior topics, merely worth a mention. There can be no right to free interstate travel
if the states retain the same authority as nation-states any more than there is
a right to travel from the U.S. to Spain, or any other independent nation.
The states would likely still accept
most federal regulations even should a right to secede be recognized, but the
fact that they could leave at any time would deprive many or most federal laws
of their practical effectiveness, because it would grant to the states, either
to the people or the legislature, a permanent veto power.
A theory of secession is
inextricably tied to the antiquated and rejected notion that the states are
independent entities bounded together simply by each one’s mutual will and
pleasure. Such an idea ignores the clear
postulate that the nation is bounded together, and ultimately accountable, to
the people as a whole, not to the states.
The federal government is ordained by the people, accountable to the
people, and supreme over the states. The
states have no power to disintegrate a union that they did not create. Rather, the people molded the states into a
new form, bounded together absent their consent as sovereign nations. The people constituted a new sovereign, whose
collective power overrode the fractured, disjointed powers of the states.
“We the
People…do ordain and establish this Constitution for the United States of
America.”
The last
five words take on new meaning, then.
Those states, previously independent, are now united into a single new
entity through the ordainment and establishment of We the People.
Concessions to Federalism
A unified
country where the national is superior to the parochial does not make the
states feeble subdivisions of the federal government, necessarily. The states could still retain exclusive
control over certain areas of law and governance, as they do (or should) thanks
to the 10th Amendment.
But
Congress and the federal government as a whole are granted explicit supremacy
in their domains, making them doubtlessly superior to the states. And the collective character of those powers
speaks to the indissolubility of the union.
As such,
the states may not unilaterally leave at their pleasure, because to do so would
negate federal powers, ignoring the superiority of nation to state (and for
that matter, the superiority of people to state and nation both), and
enervating most federal powers and duties.
The articles of confederation failed precisely because the central
government could not operate on the individual citizens, and had little practical
power over the states.
Conclusion and Summary
The purpose of this essay was to
provide some philosophical and legal force to the argument in Tribe’s book,
which rests on military force
It’s a
curious claim, that the nation’s unity rests more on the threat of arms and
superior martial might than legal or even moral force. Our nation remains united because the federal
government had/has the more powerful army? Hardly a principle befitting a
democratic republic with the rule of law.
The
argument that the secession principle was settled on the battlefield—that the Union
stands because the South lost—reminds one more of an empire than a nation whose
power derives from law duly enacted from the consent of the governed.